Hunter Liu's Website

1. Some Practise with Sequences

Table of Contents | 2. Countability ≫

Back when the dinosaurs still ruled the Earth, early Man knew of the natural numbers. Somewhere along the way, people started understanding the operation of division, giving rise to fractions and rational numbers.

The Greeks knew of the existence of irrational numbers. Long after the dinosaurs disappeared, American primary education defined an irrational number to be a (real) number that was not rational. But then what is a real number? Many American primary school textbooks define a real numbers to be number that is either rational or irrational.

Perhaps you have noticed that this is rather circular, and thus we are faced with a dilemma: either irrational numbers do not actually exist and the Greeks were wrong, or they do exist but must be constructed or characterised by their relation to rational numbers. As the Greeks were undeniably infallible, the latter must be true.

Perhaps some of you have seen an alternative definition of real numbers that isn’t circular: it can be defined (loosely) as any number that admits a (potentially infinite) decimal expansion. Put another way, a real number is anything that can be approximated by a rational number to an arbitrary degree of precision. For instance, π\pi is the “limit” of the sequence 3,3.1,3.14,3.141,3.1415,3, 3.1, 3.14, 3.141, 3.1415, \ldots

In a sense, the rational numbers Q\mathbb{Q} have a lot of “holes” in them — numbers that “should” exist like π\pi, but don’t (yet).

Remark 1.

If you have studied topology before (Math 121), one way to describe how “holey” Q\mathbb{Q} is by showing that Q\mathbb{Q} is totally disconnected under the subspace topology inherited from R\mathbb{R}!

We’ll be “filling in” these holes later, as this will be important to even define things such as infinite series and integrals. For now, we’ll be doing some practise problems that involve sequences and limits.

Problem 1.

Suppose anMa_n\leq M for some fixed MM and for all nn. Suppose additionally that a1a2a3a_1\leq a_2\leq a_3\leq\cdots. Show that given any ϵ>0\epsilon>0 that nϵ\exists n_\epsilon such that an1an2<ϵ\left\lvert a _{n_1} - a _{n_2} \right\rvert< \epsilon for all n1,n2nϵn_1, n_2\geq n _{\epsilon}.

Hint

Use a proof by contraposition! Keep the assumptions of the statement, but negate the conclusion. Suppose that {an}\left\lbrace a_n \right\rbrace is as in the problem statement, but suppose that there exists some ϵ>0\epsilon > 0 such that for every nn, there exist n1,n2nn_1, n_2\geq n such that an1an2ϵ\left\lvert a _{n_1} - a _{n_2} \right\rvert \geq \epsilon.

The main idea of a proof by contraposition is: if you are trying to prove the statement “PP implies QQ”, it’s the same thing as proving “not QQ implies not PP”. (This is the contrapositive of the original statement.)

A good trick for negating statements is that you should turn every “for all” into a “there exists” and replace every “there exists” with a “for all” in the conclusion. Of course, you also need to flip all the inequalities.

Note: I originally called this a proof by contradiction, but it’s really not that — here, we show “not (Q) implies not (P)”, whereas a proof by contradiction is “show that (P) and not (Q) is never true”. They are very slightly different, and I’m sorry for the mistake!

Solution (Using Contrapositive)

Suppose that there exists some ϵ>0\epsilon > 0 such that for every nn, there exist n1,n2nn_1, n_2\geq n such that an1an2ϵ\left\lvert a _{n_1} - a _{n_2} \right\rvert \geq \epsilon. Fix such an ϵ\epsilon.

Let m1=1m_1=1. By assumption, there exists some n1,n2m1n_1,n_2\geq m_1 such that an1an2ϵ\left\lvert a _{n_1}-a _{n_2} \right\rvert \geq \epsilon; let m2=max(n1,n2)m_2=\max \left( n_1,n_2 \right). Then am2am1ϵa _{m_2}- a _{m_1} \geq \epsilon. (Why?)

Inductively continue this sequence: given some mim_i, one may define a mi+1m _{i+1} by repeating the above process. By assumption, there exist some n1,n2min_1,n_2\geq m_i such that an1an2>ϵ\left\lvert a _{n_1}- a _{n_2} \right\rvert> \epsilon. After selecting mi+1=max(n1,n2)m _{i+1}=\max \left( n_1, n_2 \right), we get ami+1amiϵa _{m_{i+1}} - a _{m_i} \geq \epsilon.

We have now found a subsequence {ami}\left\lbrace a _{m_i} \right\rbrace such that each term increases by at least ϵ\epsilon. But this means that the sequence {an} \left\lbrace a_n \right\rbrace is unbounded! This proves the contrapositive of the problem. \square

Solution (Direct Proof)

Fix any ϵ>0\epsilon>0. Let jj be the largest integer such that MjϵM-j\epsilon is still an upper bound for the sequence {an}\left\lbrace a_n \right\rbrace. Such a jj does exist: jj is at least 00 since MM is already an upper bound, and jj cannot be larger than Manϵ\frac{M-a_n}{\epsilon} for any nn. (We are, at some level, applying the well-ordering principle here.)

Let M=MjϵM’=M-j\epsilon, which is an upper bound of {an}\left\lbrace a_n \right\rbrace. By construction, Mϵ=M(j+1)ϵM’-\epsilon=M-(j+1)\epsilon cannot be an upper bound of {an}\left\lbrace a_n \right\rbrace, so there exists some nϵn_\epsilon such that anϵMϵa _{n_\epsilon}\geq M’-\epsilon. But then ana_n is between MϵM’-\epsilon and MM’ for all nnϵn\geq n_\epsilon! It follows that for any n1n2nϵn_1\geq n_2\geq n_\epsilon, an1an2=an1an2M(Mϵ)=ϵ.\left\lvert a _{n_1}-a _{n_2} \right\rvert=a _{n_1}-a _{n_2}\leq M’-\left( M’-\epsilon \right)=\epsilon. \square

Some Comments

Some people tried using a direct proof that used a least upper bound of the sequence. This is good because if M0M_0 is the least upper bound, then for every ϵ>0\epsilon>0, there exists an nϵn_\epsilon such that anϵ>M0ϵa _{n_\epsilon}>M_0-\epsilon; this is what makes our argument work. However, we have not constructed the real numbers yet, and we cannot use least upper bounds!

At the end of the day, the two proofs have very similar flavours. The first proof argues that if the conclusion is false, then the sequence will “step up” by ϵ\epsilon infinitely many times, contradicting boundedness. The second proof argues that if the sequence is bounded, one can lower the bound to “within an ϵ\epsilon” of the sequence, which allows us to control how spread out the sequence is.

Problem 2.

Given two monotone nondecreasing sequences {an}\left\lbrace a_n \right\rbrace and {bn}\left\lbrace b_n \right\rbrace each bounded above, define a relation {an}{bn}\left\lbrace a_n \right\rbrace\sim \left\lbrace b_n \right\rbrace if limnanbn=0\lim _{n\to\infty} \left\lvert a_n-b_n \right\rvert=0. Determine if the following statement is true or false:

If {an}{bn}\left\lbrace a_n \right\rbrace\sim \left\lbrace b_n \right\rbrace and {cn}{dn}\left\lbrace c_n \right\rbrace\sim \left\lbrace d_n \right\rbrace, then {an+cn}{bn+dn}\left\lbrace a_n+c_n \right\rbrace\sim \left\lbrace b_n+d_n \right\rbrace.

Hint
Try using the triangle inequality: for any nn, one has that (an+cn)(bn+dn)=(anbn)+(cndn)anbn+cndn.\left\lvert \left( a_n+c_n \right)- \left( b_n+d_n \right) \right\rvert = \left\lvert \left( a_n-b_n \right) + \left( c_n-d_n \right) \right\rvert \leq \left\lvert a_n-b_n \right\rvert+ \left\lvert c_n-d_n \right\rvert. Try employing a direct proof by unwrapping the definition of a limit. How can we use this triangle inequality to our advantage?
Solution

By definition, {an+cn}{bn+dn}\left\lbrace a_n+c_n \right\rbrace\sim \left\lbrace b_n+d_n \right\rbrace if limn(an+cn)(bn+dn)=0\lim _{n\to\infty} \left\lvert \left( a_n+c_n \right)-\left( b_n+d_n \right) \right\rvert=0. By definition, this means that for each ϵ>0\epsilon>0 there exists some nϵn _{\epsilon} such that for all n>nϵn > n _{\epsilon}, (an+cn)(bn+dn)<ϵ.\left\lvert \left( a_n+c_n \right)-\left( b_n+d_n \right) \right\rvert< \epsilon. By the triangle inequality (see the hint above), we have that (an+cn)(bn+dn)=(anbn)+(cndn)anbn+cndn.\left\lvert \left( a_n+c_n \right)- \left( b_n+d_n \right) \right\rvert = \left\lvert \left( a_n-b_n \right) + \left( c_n-d_n \right) \right\rvert \leq \left\lvert a_n-b_n \right\rvert+ \left\lvert c_n-d_n \right\rvert. The idea is that both quantities at the very right should “eventually be very small”, and this forces the quantity at the left to be “eventually be very small” as well. This is what we want!

Fix an ϵ>0\epsilon>0. Since {an}{bn}\left\lbrace a_n \right\rbrace\sim \left\lbrace b_n \right\rbrace, limnanbn=0\lim _{n\to\infty} \left\lvert a_n-b_n \right\rvert=0. Thus, there exists some N1N_1 such that whenever nN1n\geq N_1, anbn<ϵ2\left\lvert a_n-b_n \right\rvert < \frac{\epsilon}{2} . Similarly, since {cn}{dn}\left\lbrace c_n \right\rbrace\sim \left\lbrace d_n \right\rbrace, limncndn=0\lim _{n\to\infty}\left\lvert c_n-d_n \right\rvert=0, so there exists some N2N_2 so that whenever nN2n\geq N_2, cndn<ϵ2\left\lvert c_n-d_n \right\rvert< \frac{\epsilon}{2} .

Let nϵ=max(N1,N2)n _{\epsilon}=\max\left( N_1,N_2 \right). If nnϵn \geq n _{\epsilon}, then nN1n\geq N_1, so anbn<ϵ2\left\lvert a_n-b_n \right\rvert < \frac{\epsilon}{2}. Similarly, if nnϵn\geq n _{\epsilon}, then nN2n\geq N_2, so cndn<ϵ2\left\lvert c_n-d_n \right\rvert< \frac{\epsilon}{2} as well. Using the triangle inequality from before, we get that for all nnϵn \geq n _{\epsilon} that (an+cn)(bn+dn)<=anbn+cndn<ϵ2+ϵ2=ϵ.\left\lvert \left( a_n+c_n \right)-\left( b_n+d_n \right) \right\rvert <= \left\lvert a_n-b_n \right\rvert+\left\lvert c_n-d_n \right\rvert< \frac{\epsilon}{2}+\frac{\epsilon}{2}=\epsilon. This works for any ϵ>0\epsilon>0, so we conclude that limn(an+cn)(bn+dn)=0\lim _{n\to\infty}\left\lvert \left( a_n+c_n \right)-\left( b_n+d_n \right) \right\rvert=0. Thus, {an+bn}{cn+dn}\left\lbrace a_n+b_n \right\rbrace\sim \left\lbrace c_n+d_n \right\rbrace by definition. \square

Problem 3.

This problem is not directly related to this class, but it is a fun exercise that demonstrates a method of proof the other problems don’t use.

In a set of any six people named A,B,C,D,E,FA, B, C, D, E, F, show that there is a subset of three people that either all know each other or are all strangers to each other.

Hint
Try splitting this problem into cases based on how many people AA knows. What happens if they know 33 or more people? What happens if they know fewer than 33 people?
Solution

Let’s consider two cases:

  1. AA knows at least 33 other people.
  2. AA knows fewer than 33 other people. Necessarily, this means that AA doesn’t know at least 33 other people.

Case 1: Suppose AA knows at least 33 other people. Without loss of generality, we may assume that AA knows BB, CC, and DD. If BB, CC, and DD all don’t know each other, then we’ve found three people that don’t know each other. Otherwise, at least two of them know each other, say BB and CC, hence A,BA, B, and CC all know each other!

The second case is more or less the same argument.

Case 2: Suppose AA doesn’t know at least 33 other people. Again, we may assume that AA doesn’t recognise BB, CC, and DD. If these three strangers to AA all know each other, we’re done! Otherwise, at least two of them don’t know each other, say BB and CC; thus AA, BB, and CC are all strangers to each other. \square

Problem 4.

Let {an}\left\lbrace a_n \right\rbrace be any sequence such that anM\left\lvert a_n \right\rvert\leq M for some MM and all nn. Show that there exists a subsequence {anj}\left\lbrace a _{n_j} \right\rbrace that is either monotone nonincreasing or monotone nondecreasing.

Note: this statement is often described as the “scenic viewpoint theorem”. Where do you think the name comes from?

Hint
Define a scenic viewpoint to be an index NN such that anaNa_n\leq a_N whenever nNn\geq N. In a sense, aNa_N “overlooks” the rest of the sequence. Now split your proof into cases depending on how many scenic viewpoints the sequence admits.
Solution

Following the hint, we’ll consider two cases:

  1. The sequence {an}\left\lbrace a_n \right\rbrace has infinitely many scenic viewpoints.
  2. The sequence {an}\left\lbrace a_n \right\rbrace has finitely many scenic viewpoints.

Case 1: Let n1n_1 be the first scenic viewpoint, n2n_2 be the second scenic viewpoint, etc. Then {anj}\left\lbrace a _{n_j} \right\rbrace is a monotone nonincreasing subsequence — each scenic viewpoint “overlooks” the rest of them!

Case 2: Let NN be the last scenic viewpoint in the sequence. Let n1>Nn_1>N. n1n_1 can’t be a scenic viewpoint since it’s beyond the last scenic viewpoint in the sequence. Thus, there exists some n2>n1n_2>n_1 with an2>an1a _{n_2} > a _{n_1}. But n2n_2 is also past the last scenic viewpoint, so it isn’t a scenic viewpoint!

We can repeat this construction inductively to produce a monotone increasing subsequence. Given the jj-th term njn_j of the subsequence, we know that it must be past the last scenic viewpoint and hence isn’t a scenic viewpoint itself. Thus, there exists some nj+1>njn _{j+1}> n_j such that anj+1>anja _{n _{j+1}} > a _{n_j}.

By construction, we see that {anj}\left\lbrace a _{n_j} \right\rbrace is a monotone increasing subsequence, concluding the second case. \square